HOW THE U.S. SHOULD DEAL WITH THE NEW EGYPT

By Dr. Tawfik Hamid, Senior Fellow and Chair of the Study of Islamic Radicalism at the Potomac Institute for Policy Studies

Retrieved on 31 January 2012 from: www.tawfikhamid.com–this commentary has undergone minor editing.

The current situation in Egypt has created new challenges for the U.S. and needs careful calculations for proper progress. On one hand the U.S wants stability in the country, while on the other hand it supports democracy, which will ultimately empower suppressive Islamic regimes and threaten the U.S. interests in the area.

At the moment there are three powers that claim legitimacy in Egypt, these being: the Army, the Islamist-led parliament, and the young revolutionists of Tahrir Square. Each of these factions believes that it is the legitimate power. The Supreme Council of the Armed Forces (SCAF) feels as though they are the ones who made the revolution successful, as they supported the population against Mubarak. The young revolutionists of Tahrir Square believe that they are the ones who created the revolution and thus they must have a share in power (currently they have less than three percent representation in the Parliament). The Islamists believe that they are the only legitimate power, as they have risen through the ballot elections.

Among these groups the army is still the only force that has held long and relatively stable relations with the U.S. and thus can protect its interests in the area. Unfortunately, the Military’s nonchalant attitude, and lengthy trial, of Mubarak and his family among many other terrible decisions has created a strong wave of antagonism against the SCAF among the population. Despite this, for a multitude of different reasons, the Military still enjoys an immense amount of popularity within the country.

The Islamists that dominate the new Egyptian parliament have not clarified their position on major issues, such as the peace treaty with Israel. In fact, in the recent anniversary of the January 25, 2011, revolution, the Muslim Brotherhood (MB) members were shouting slogans that were supportive of the Nazi ideology. These include: “Hitler Basha Alha Zaman…El-Sohuni Lazem Yethan” which means “Hitler Basha (an Arabic word of praise) said it (correctly) in the past…any Zionist must be humiliated.” The context of these slogans was to commend Hitler’s actions against the Jews.

If the moment arises when the Islamists seize all the power, i.e., control the military, intelligence, and police, it will be extremely difficult to stop them from transforming the country to be similar to Iran or even worse. The existence of the Military in a position to have full control over the armed forces is the best option for the U.S. to protect its interests in this vicinity (despite the mistakes of the SCAF). If the U.S. lets the army down and pressures them to hand the power completely over to the civilians, it will be risking its foreign interests. In this case it is likely to face a more vicious, religiously-based fascism replacing the Military suppression of the population. It would be significantly easier to deal with the latter than with the former.

The third group, the young liberal revolutionists, are very passionate about democracy, however, they lack the necessary experience needed to rule the country and do not have apparent leaders. Many of them divert their energy only against the Military and completely ignore the Islamist threat upon the nation. In addition, these youth have yet to gain the support of a large majority.

The U.S. needs to have a distinctive strategy to deal with these groups, showing support for the army as long as they maintain the secularism of the country and protect U.S. interests in the region.

On one hand the U.S. should show respect to the Islamists, and on the other hand it must be very clear that the Islamists cannot get any support from the U.S. if they do not clarify their current ambiguous position on respecting the previous international commitments of the country, including the peace treaty with Israel. The U.S. needs to ask the MB leaders to clarify their position from the recent pro-Nazi slogans that were used by their members in Tahrir Square on the recent anniversary of the revolution. It will be completely irresponsible to use American tax-payer dollars to support a regime led by people who encourage pro-Nazi slogans.

At the moment the MB is facing several challenges. These include:

  1. Possible confrontation with the Military if the MB insists on not giving the Military certain privileges in the new Egypt.
  2. An impatient population that will expect the Muslim Brotherhood-led parliament to bring a fast solution to the already declining economy.
  3. Salafi groups who will insist on a very strict interpretation of Islam. For example, the Salafi groups have already started to object to accepting loans from international banks, as they see it as Rebba (usury) which is “Haram” or forbidden in Islam.
  4. The young revolutionists who accuse them of betraying the revolution. In fact, in the recent demonstrations the revolutionists physically attacked members of the MB, raised their shoes against them (a very insulting thing to do in the Arab culture), and cursed them loudly in public prayer which was joined by thousands.
  5. Divisions within the Brotherhood, as several young members have begun to feel that their leadership was losing their moral character. For example, the daughter of Akram AL-Sheer (a leading member within the MB) had a fight over the phone with the Murshid (supreme guide) of the MB and decided to resign from the organization after he hung up the phone.

All these factors have put the MB in a situation where they cannot fail in bringing rapid economic success for the country; otherwise, the above powers will unite against it and end their political dream to rule the country.

The U.S. should use this moment to its benefit, as the MB is starting to worry that they may not be able to solve the current economic problems of Egypt. Recently, the MB began to say that no single faction in the society can solve the problems in the country by itself. This has been said to escape from being entirely responsible if the economy falls even steeper after they come to power, as their failure will abort their dream to prove that “Islam is the solution.”

The current situation gives the U.S. an advantage over the MB, as the group will not risk Egypt losing billions of dollars in U.S. aid and other forms of support. Losing such a large monetary amount can significantly threaten their political future and risk the concept of Islamic revival.  In fact, one of the most effective ways to tame the MB is to notify them that if they work against U.S. interests or break the former commitments of the country, the U.S. aid that typically goes to Egypt will go to Israel instead. This will place the MB in a situation where any decision that they may initiate against U.S. interests will turn out to be beneficial to whom they consider to be their worst enemy, Israel.

In addition, The U.S. needs to direct the various human rights organizations, which are supported by U.S. federal money, to have a strong humanitarian arm that plays a more social role within society. This could include food banks to distribute low-cost food to the poor and supporting their creation of small projects. The organizations in Egypt that are supported by the U.S. must give more care to such humanitarian efforts, so that secularists and liberals can defeat the Islamists in the next elections – rather than putting their main focus on standing against the Military. The latter approach pushes the Military toward the Islamists and risks bringing full power to the more suppressive  Islamists, who will overpower the population in the name of Islam.

In conclusion, the current complex situation in Egypt needs a U.S. strategy that puts its interests as a priority and deals with the current realities. The U.S. needs to back the Military in having full control over the armed forces (as long as they keep the US interests in the region), to use the power of U.S. aid to Egypt to influence the MB, and to direct the U.S.-financed organizations in the country to give more care to humanitarian, rather than political, efforts.

Dr/ Tawfik Hamid is a Senior Fellow and Chair of the Study of Radical Islamic Radicalism at the Potomac Institute for Policy Studies. He is an Islamic thinker and reformer and one-time Islamic extremist from Egypt. He was a member of a terrorist Islamic organization, al-Jamaat al-Islamiya (JI), with Dr. Ayman Al-Zawaherri, who later became the second in command of Al-Qaeda.

Some twenty-five years ago, Dr. Hamid recognized the threat of Radical Islam and the need for a reformation based upon modern peaceful interpretations of classical Islamic core texts. He provided a fresh and theologically valid interpretation for the Qur’an to counterbalance the radical teaching. As the Daily Express (UK) mentioned “Dr. Hamid has predicted the attacks on the twin towers, Madrid and London.” After September 11, Dr. Hamid boldly decided to speak out through western broadcast and print media. He has appeared on shows spanning the spectrum from CNN to Fox News, and his articles and op-ed pieces have appeared in publications such as the Wall Street Journal, the New York Daily News, and the Jerusalem Post. Some of Dr. Hamid’s Op-Eds were also selected at Real Clear Politics. He has been a guest speaker both within the U.S. and internationally, before audiences such as the U.S. Congress, Director of National Intelligence, the Pentagon, the National Prayer breakfast, and the European Parliament. He is the author of the author of Inside Jihad: Understanding and Confronting Radical Islam (2008), which is available from Amazon Books

THE FALL OF THE MODERN AGE? A REVIEW OF “THE SEARCH FOR MEANING IN AN UNCERTAIN WORLD”

By Neil G. Robertson, Ph.D., Associate Professor, University of King’s College, Halifax

A review of Icarus Fallen: The Search for Meaning in an Uncertain World
by Chantal Delsol, ISI Books, 2003, from Intercollegiate Review, Fall/Winter 2004

After more than three decades of a constant stream of French post-modernist theory, for many of us the identification of contemporary French thought with post-modernity has become nearly complete. It is therefore with a certain sense of wonderment, or at least curiosity, that one must greet the publication of this translation of Chantal Delsol’s explicitly un-post-modern contemplation of “contemporary man” and the cultural situation in which he finds himself. For Delsol, contemporary man is not flying high in the ether of deconstruction, difference, and the endless play of meaning. Rather, he is an Icarus fallen, a creature whose wings have melted from flying too close to the sun and who now walks confused and disillusioned in the labyrinth of the very human condition from which he sought escape. From this perspective post-modernity is but a final form of modernity—broken wings flapping wildly. For Delsol, such efforts to fly from reality have come to an end. The truth of the contemporary situation is that we stand disappointed and disoriented in a world we hardly recognize as our own, clinging to principles and postures we know at the same time to be empty and vain.

Delsol is clearly a formidable person. She is the mother of a small tribe of children, the wife of a controversial conservative French politician, and is involved in religious concerns, specifically contemporary Catholicism. Professionally, she is a university professor, a respected novelist, and a noted contributor to French political thought. In the latter field she has been particularly involved in questions of European federalism and in efforts to apply the originally Catholic concept of subsidiarity to the contemporary political world. Thus, she has been a critic of the centralizing tendencies both within France and in the European Union. In short, while she is a critic of “contemporary man,” she is also— and knows herself to be—fully a “contemporary.” As she puts it, “I obviously do not feel that I am essentially any different from the contemporary man of which I write.”

She describes Icarus Fallen as “very much a sociology of the mind.” Her intent in this work is to elucidate the spiritual or mental standpoint in which humanity today finds itself, a standpoint which finds the world empty, or meaningless, or uncertain. Her general claim is that modernity has exposed itself, especially with the collapse of Soviet Marxism, as a failed flight from the real. As a result, the hyperbolic ideals and hopes that modernity propounded have led to a radical deflation. We now live in a strange realm of humanistic complacency, where there is a powerful morality of inclusion and equality, but without foundation or purpose. For Delsol, this late modern/ post-modern morality is ultimately a morality of withdrawal and despair. The contemporary mind is wounded, unable to look beyond its own self-satisfaction to realities that are constituting and elevating. From this point of view, the contemporary mind is a paradox: both self-satisfied and despairing, complacent and restless. However, throughout the book Delsol suggests that the contemporary is not simply this standpoint of resignation and complacency, but that there are present in it as well intimations of larger structures of reality: intimations that point to questions of good and evil, truth and falsity, the passing character of the world and the eternity of the divine.

In the face of these deeper intimations Delsol ends the book with a call to a new vigilance and a new sense of responsibility. Contemporary man needs to live more directly and openly within the fragility and contradictions of existence. Refreshingly, she does not call for a simple repudiation of the modern and a simple return to pre-modern forms of meaning and significance. As she states, “The great difficulty will be to defend the gains of modernity while at the same time struggling against its excesses. For taking a simplistic approach is always the first reflex, and the great temptation of this disappointed era could easily be an overall rejection, a return to the besieged cocoon of a priori certitudes, or purity-seeking fundamentalism, which is just another form of utopian delusion.”

This is a beautifully written and finely translated book that falls within the French essai genre. As such, it is written in a direct and meditative fashion, without the normal scholarly apparatus. While this approach is very appealing, especially for the common reader, it does have its frustrations. I would have valued learning about Delsol’s view of how she is situated in the long tradition of the critique of modernity. For it is here that I have my most basic question for this book. Let me state bluntly what I take to be the general tenor of the critique of modernity: Modernity seeks to establish an impossible standpoint which leads to its own undoing, evidenced by a situation of nihilism, meaninglessness, and despair; this in turn points us to an abiding standpoint beyond the modern, return to which provides us with renewed structures of significance. [emphasis added] Such an account may be found in a multitude of figures throughout the twentieth century: T.S. Eliot, Martin Heidegger, Josef Pieper, Karl Löwith, Leo Strauss, and Alasdair MacIntyre are but a few names one could mention. So one might well ask, beyond some new images and rhetorical figures, what does Delsol have to say about the character of contemporary man that cannot be found by reading Eliot’s The Waste Land? At the most fundamental level, I would judge that there is nothing to distinguish them—putting aside the evident difference in genre. But is this to say that Delsol is simply repeating the thoughts of the great critics of modernity from the early twentieth century? No. Delsol is writing in the context of early twenty-first-century Europe, and this crucially informs the whole character and significance of her work.

But it is on this count that I would criticize this American edition of Icarus Fallen. Delsol herself tells us, “In spite of my fragmented and insufficient knowledge of North America, I am convinced that there is a similarity between your societies and our own, at least as far as this ‘sociology of the mind’ is concerned.” But I am not so convinced. Even if what she claims is true, her argument still cannot make sense to North American readers without a more extensive explanation of European political developments, and particularly French intellectual history. This is where a much more informative introduction to the book would have been a great addition.

For Delsol, the whole meaning of the fall of Icarus is the fall of Soviet Marxism. To North Americans, this defeat is a great and important event, but is so primarily in terms of a shift in geopolitics. It has not led in North America to the conviction that modernity is in crisis. Indeed, insofar as it has affected North American self-understanding, this has appeared in Francis Fukuyama’s popular “end of history” thesis: namely, the claim of the final triumph of (modern) liberal democracy. The defeat of Soviet Marxism has clarified for North Americans that their forms of government are not just one pole of the Capitalist-Communist dialectic, but rather are self-standing wholes capable of bringing civil order and contentment to modern life.

Thus, I would argue that Icarus has not fallen in North America; if anything, the fall of Soviet Marxism has brought forth a bolder, more confident modernity here. By contrast, for Delsol, coming out of the tradition of twentieth-century French political thought, modernity is essentially identified with Marxism. Consequently, Icarus really did fall in 1989. While North Americans have never seriously been attracted to  the extreme politics that have been so powerful in Europe throughout the twentieth century, much of French intellectual life has been, for at least fifty years, essentially post-liberal, and so fundamentally critical of the relation of society and government characteristic of liberal democracies. For the North American reader to really follow Delsol’s argument and its specific import, this larger intellectual and political context needs to be brought out. Of course, behind my criticism is the claim that Delsol’s argument is not directly translatable to the North American context; she and the editors of Icarus Fallen may well have judged otherwise.

Such a judgment is certainly not without some warrant. After all, so much of North American social, intellectual, and moral life seems to be found in the pages of this evocative text. Certainly conservatives will find much here that resonates with their intuitions and daily experience. Delsol does bring out with real delicacy the ambiguous, tentative stance many in the contemporary world find themselves adopting. We know the failure of the radical politics that so enlivened the twentieth century, the failure of radical secular humanism: and yet we seem unable to return to the older forms of thought and belief that can give place and order to our lives. We seek structures of significance: and yet, as soon as they become determinate, we flee them as oppressive and limiting. Delsol herself can only point to this dilemma without actually resolving it, for she guards against any direct turn to metaphysics or theology. She points to the need, as she puts it, “to defend the gains of modernity”: modernity in its failure exposes an abiding principle, but now one that we, as moderns, must come to know for ourselves, through a tentative, exploratory “new anthropology.”

But is this tentativeness itself not yet another form of the contemporary malaise Delsol works to expose? My own judgment is that while North Americans have tendencies towards the “contemporary man” that Delsol describes and seeks to overcome, fundamentally we North Americans are already beyond this European condition; we live with a straightforward confidence in our institutions and religions that seems altogether impossible to contemporary Europeans. But is this claim true? It is precisely in forcing us to confront our ambivalent intuitions that we can see the virtue and importance of Icarus Fallen. This book brings to the North American reader a searching and powerful account of the contemporary European soul, and then asks that reader whether he too finds himself reflected there.

Neil G. Robertson is an Associate Professor in the Foundation Year, Early Modern Studies and Contemporary Studies programs. Dr. Robertson graduated from the University of King’s College in 1985 with a BA in Political Science. He went on to take an M.A. in Classics at Dalhousie University, and in 1995 completed his PhD at Cambridge in Social and Political Science. He has held the position of Director of the Foundation Year Program and is past Director of the Early Modern Studies Program, which he helped to found. Dr. Robertson was the King’s College Dean of Residence in 1989-1990 and has been Chair of Faculty since 2001.

This review is republished from the Fall/Winter 2004 edition of Intercollegiate Review, published by the Intercollegiate Studies Institute (ISI). Copyright 2004. Used by permission. ISI is a nonprofit, nonpartisan, tax-exempt educational organization that seeks to educate future leaders in the timeless principles that make America free and prosperous—the core ideas behind the free market, the American Founding, and Western civilization that are rarely taught in the classroom. The website address of ISI is: http://home.isi.org

REPUBLICAN VIRTUE, IMPERIAL TEMPTATIONS, A REVIEW OF “THE CRISIS OF DEMOCRACY AND THE QUEST FOR EMPIRE”

“While seeming to defend the Western tradition from its enemies, New Jacobins advance a ‘secular, ahistorical, and egalitarian’ appropriation of that tradition. Despite their rhetoric of piety toward tradition, they are the enemies of ‘pre-Enlightenment Western civilization.’ Whereas America’s ‘old moral ethos’ acknowledged the binding authority of tradition and custom and the contingencies of particular circumstances, Neo-Jacobin consciousness is ahistorical, universalist, and driven towards greater and greater concentrations of power.” –an excerpt from this review

by Richard Gamble, Associate Professor of History, Hillsdale College

A review of America the Virtuous: The Crisis of Democracy and the Quest for Empire
by Claes G. Ryn Transaction Press, 2003, from Intercollegiate Review, Fall/Winter 2004

Many Enlightenment ideologues hoped to see fulfilled in America all the dreams of the Age of Reason: an empire of unfettered minds, natural rights, unbounded human benevolence and progress, the first fruits of a world reborn. Impatient utopians soon despaired, however. Faced with ratification of a conservative Constitution rooted in the long Western tradition of classical and Christian civilization, they turned their imaginations to the promise of revolutionary France. Nevertheless, some Americans persisted in their secular millennial expectations for the United States. Foremost among these at the opening of the twenty-first century are those whom Claes Ryn calls “new Jacobins.” In America the Virtuous, Ryn analyzes the defining elements of their worldview. In his own words, his “study aims to identify, illustrate, and analyze a general ideological phenomenon, a powerful tendency of thought, imagination and action with its own distinctive logic and momentum.” That tendency, in Ryn’s estimation, is leading America toward profound disorder.

Neo-Jacobinism, like its original embodiment more than two centuries ago in revolutionary France, displaces a concrete, localized, rooted, classical and Christian view of man and society with an abstract, universalized, restless, Enlightenment and Romantic view. To some degree, Ryn is carrying into the twenty-first century the ideological argument between Edmund Burke and Jean-Jacques Rousseau. Ryn stands with Burke, Irving Babbitt, Wilhelm Roepke, and Russell Kirk against Rousseau, John Locke, the French revolutionaries, and—perhaps surprising to many conservatives—Leo Strauss, and, particularly, Allan Bloom. While he does not hesitate to name names, Ryn’s “primary purpose is not to classify particular individuals but to identify a particular intellectual-political dynamic with its own inner logic, to show how certain ideas belong together and form a coherent, if philosophically highly questionable, ideology.”

The strength of Ryn’s analysis is his identification of deep discontinuities in American history and experience: namely, transformations of leadership, ethical conduct, political philosophy, social and economic structures, language, historical consciousness, and national self-perception and ambitions. Ryn roots American civilization in the heritage of Greece and Rome, Western Christendom, and British culture. America emerged from a particular past, a concrete  historical experience. America is indebted to that past for its culture, political institutions, and freedoms.

New Jacobins, however, viewing the past as a dark prison from which humanity must be liberated, construct an alternative America that fulfills Enlightenment dreams of emancipation, abstract natural rights, and unbridled democratism. Their interpretations of the American founding, canon of state documents, and cultural identity— while perhaps ideologically alluring—are at odds with historical reality. While seeming to advocate “traditional values,” they are actually revolutionaries who subvert the decentralist constitutional democracy of the founders. While seeming to defend the Western tradition from its enemies, New Jacobins advance a “secular, ahistorical, and egalitarian” appropriation of that tradition. Despite their rhetoric of piety toward tradition, they are the enemies of “pre-Enlightenment Western civilization.” Whereas America’s “old moral ethos” acknowledged the binding authority of tradition and custom and the contingencies of particular circumstances, Neo-Jacobin consciousness is ahistorical, universalist, and driven towards greater and greater concentrations of power. In fact, Ryn argues, “what the new Jacobins defend as Western civilization is actually but a small and relatively recent part of it, chiefly that part which came to political prominence with the French Revolution and that finds its other beginnings in the rationalism of the eighteenth-century Enlightenment and its precursors.”

If America is an “idea,” as the new Jacobins insist, then it is properly defined, now and always, by exceptionalism, universalism, democratism, restless innovation, and ideological imperialism. To the new Jacobin mind, the American story is one of unbroken, triumphalist continuity and robust good health. If, on the other hand, as Ryn contends, America over the past two centuries has actually abandoned its moorings and jettisoned the ballast of its classical and Christian heritage, then the American story is discontinuous and headed, perhaps, to an unhappy ending. Most alarmingly, America has abandoned its longstanding fear of power and pride; instead, “the signs are now everywhere that the will to dominate is breaking free of such traditional restraints.” Ryn blames the new Jacobinism for transforming the more modest old republic into an aggressive, ideological, revolutionary state bent on empire and driven to remake the world in its own image.

Ryn’s analysis is disturbing and provocative. It provides a framework within which to organize a range of slogans and policies into a coherent pattern of thought and conduct. From one angle, however, there is something inescapably authentic about the neo-Jacobin temptation. While recent enthusiasms for America as a messianic “universal nation” may represent a discontinuity from earlier American self-conceptions, there are also clearly continuities here, and these continuities need to be exposed and their implications understood. This is not a criticism of Ryn’s painstaking analysis, but a doorway into further in•quiry, perhaps of a more historical nature.

What do we make of, and what do we do, with the messianic, meliorist, liberationist impulse that in one form or another, to one degree or another, has been with us for four hundred years? A type of redemptive universalism came to the New World with the Puritans and reappeared from time to time even among the most sober-minded of the founders. From “God’s American Israel” to Crèvecoeur’s “new man,” from Yankee nation-building in the Civil War to Wilsonian social-gospel globalism in World War I, America has wrestled with this expansionist revolutionary tendency. There is something about Jacobinism that is persistently and in some sense genuinely American. At the dawn of the twenty-first century we are perhaps merely witnessing the further evolution of a contagion that we have carried in us from the beginning. Doctrines and impulses that we once consciously and deliberately suppressed are now allowed to run free. A more extended analysis of how and when these checks were removed in our history may provide a key to reinstating these checks institutionally, culturally, and personally.

Ryn has not written a book for the lazy, impatient, or haphazard reader. As hard as it may be for his likely opponents to accept, his analysis is refreshingly non-ideological. He ponders his subject with impressive care and attention, taking time to define terms, to trace the redefinition of familiar terms, to establish context and proper categories, to reaffirm hierarchies of obligation, to dichotomize between true and false notions of particular principles, and to distinguish between appearance and reality. Despite its provocative thesis and bold analysis, Ryn’s is in fact a cautious book that patiently makes its case, limits its implications, guards the careful reader from misinterpretations, and points out wherever necessary what it is not saying. Anticipating misunderstanding, Ryn frames and fences his argument at every turn. A proper reading of this book requires the all-too-rare mental habits of attention, discrimination, and judgment.

Ryn offers more than diagnosis, however, and his book is infused by hope. This is not a work of despair and cynicism, nor is Ryn nostalgic for a world lost beyond recovery. Indeed, he sees little left for conservatism to conserve. Despite the dreams of mere traditionalists, “the old Western civilization cannot return. It has been too badly damaged.” Instead, the task is one of reconstitution of the cultural preconditions of the well-ordered city. To that end, American civilization needs to re-appropriate the best of the Western tradition to meet new times and circumstances. Urgently, America requires “a new moral realism,” a foreign policy based on what Ryn calls “responsible nationhood,” and a return to limits personally and nationally, including “the rediscovery of responsibilities that are near, immediate, and concrete.”

The task, then, is not to win elections and capture positions of political power, but to renew the culture. The greatest responsibility rests with those who help shape the mind and imagination of the rising generations to offer them a coherent, compelling alternative. America requires the reaffirmation, by each of us, of the qualities of character necessary for authentic constitutional self-government—modesty, discipline, demonstrated ability, and a due sense of limits and proportion.

America the Virtuous calls for critical self-examination. It leads us to meditate on the contours of America’s past and present. Ryn equips us with an analytical tool that may provide a way of rethinking and retelling at least one part of the American story. He leads us as well to ponder the future of these tendencies, the implications for the nation if Jacobinism triumphs, completing the uprooting of America from the principles that once ordered its civilization. At a historical moment when the American people are being told that their Declaration of Independence and their Constitution embody political principles that ought to govern all peoples in all times and places and that Americans are the global guarantors of God-given rights, Ryn calls us back to constitutionalism and away from empire, back to character and away from sentiment.

Richard M. Gamble is Associate Professor of History at HIllsdale College, Michigan and the author of The War for Righteousness: Progressive Christianity, the Great War, and the Rise of the Messianic Nation (2003) and of a forthcoming book entitled The Search for the City on a Hill: The Making and Unmaking of an American Myth (to be released in August 2012).

This review was first published in the Fall/Winter 2004 edition of Intercollegiate Review, published by the Intercollegiate Studies Institute (ISI). Used by permission. ISI is a nonprofit, nonpartisan, tax-exempt educational organization that seeks to educate future leaders in the timeless principles that make America free and prosperous—the core ideas behind the free market, the American Founding, and Western civilization that are rarely taught in the classroom..The website address of ISI is: http://home.isi.org

THE MORAL MEANING OF AMERICA: A REVIEW OF “LINCOLN AT PEORIA….”

“Throughout our history there will always be the likes of Stephen A. Douglas who seek to evade difficult moral issues through an appeal to relativism. The character of each generation may be measured in terms of whether or not we choose to confront these issues in the manner of Douglas or of Lincoln.” –an excerpt from this essay

by Joseph R. Fornieri, Professor of Political Science, Rochester Institute of Technology

A review of Lincoln at Peoria: The Turning Point: Getting Right with the Declaration of Independence by Lewis E. Lehrman (Mechanicsburg, PA: Stackpole Books, 2008) from Intercollegiate Review, Spring 2009

What is Abraham Lincoln’s greatest speech? An obvious case can be made for the Gettysburg Address, which distills the essence of the American creed and has come to represent the catechism of our civil religion, “of the people, by the people, for the people.” Others claim that the honor belongs to the Second Inaugural Address. In that national sermon, Lincoln pondered the meaning of the Civil War in view of God’s providence. The speech culminates in a magnanimous call to righteousness and reconciliation: “With malice toward none, with charity for all, with firmness in the right as God gives us to see the right, let us strive on to finish the work we are in, to bind up the nation’s wounds.” Still others argue that the Cooper Union Address was Lincoln’s greatest since it was “the speech that made him president”: “Let us have faith that right makes might, and in that faith, let us, to the end, dare to do our duty as we understand it.”

Notwithstanding these others, if one were placed in the unenviable position of having to choose Lincoln’s greatest, I would cast my vote for the Peoria Address of October 16, 1854. At Peoria, Lincoln cogently articulated the core antislavery convictions that would guide his statesmanship for the rest of his life. This articulation involved a corresponding vindication of self-government and the Union. In a word, the Peoria Address constituted the most mature and vivid expression of Lincoln’s political faith or ultimate moral justification of American public life based upon the principles of the Declaration. Indeed, Lincoln’s subsequent speeches and writings drew upon the comprehensive and foundational antislavery teachings he expounded at Peoria.

It is therefore surprising that in the voluminous Lincoln literature there has been no full-length, single-volume treatment of this critical speech. Though it was recognized by Lincoln’s contemporaries as a tour de force, it has since been eclipsed by attention given to his other major speeches. In Lincoln at Peoria: The Turning Point, Lewis Lehrman remedies this omission by persuasively showing us why the Peoria Address deserves its rightful place as one of Lincoln’s greatest statements. Lehrman’s meticulously researched and elegantly written book makes a significant contribution towards enhancing our understanding of the moral dimensions of Lincoln’s political thought and statesmanship. It is highly recommended for students and scholars alike.

Lehrman’s outstanding study integrates and builds upon insights from the fields of history, political science, and political philosophy. He begins by tracing the historical and political context of the Peoria Address as a response to the infamous Kansas-Nebraska Act of 1854 that repealed the Missouri Compromise of 1820. This latter measure had maintained a fragile sectional peace for more than thirty years by drawing a line through the remaining territories of the Louisiana Purchase: slavery was banned north of 36˚30’ but tolerated south of it. The repeal of the Missouri Compromise stirred Lincoln to reenter politics in response to a new militancy of the proslavery forces that threatened both the moral and territorial integrity of the Union. “I was losing interest in politics,” he declared, “when the Missouri Compromise aroused me again.”

The Peoria Address can be seen as a prelude to the famous Lincoln-Douglas debates of 1858. It was at Peoria in 1854 where the two titans first crossed swords over slavery and popular sovereignty. At Peoria, in response to the Kansas-Nebraska Act, Lincoln offered his first comprehensive indictment of slavery and defense of America’s free institutions. After Peoria, he would emerge as the standard-bearer of the antislavery Republican Party in Illinois and ultimately the president of the United States in 1860. “The three-hour Peoria speech was a magisterial tour of antislavery principles, their constitutional and legislative history, and the antislavery policies of the federal government from the Founding through the Kansas-Nebraska Act,” Lehrman writes. “At this turning point in American history, Lincoln queried whether America was destined to become a free-soil republic or a slaveholding nation. Throughout his remarks, he celebrated the intent of the Founders to put slavery in the course of ultimate extinction.”

Lehrman tells the story of this turning point in an engaging narrative that brings to life the cast of characters of the Civil War era: Lincoln, Douglas, Chase, Seward, Stevens, Davis. Though much has been made of Lincoln’s ambition or melancholy as a spur to his greatness, Lehrman reminds us that more principled motives were at work as well. Those who would deny the sincerity and depth of Lincoln’s hatred of slavery and his corresponding patriotic devotion to the American experiment are confronted in Lehrman’s superb book with a mountain of evidence to the contrary, as when Lincoln exclaimed:

This declared indifference [of popular sovereignty to the evil of slavery], but as I must think, covert real zeal for the spread of slavery, I can not but hate. I hate it because of the monstrous injustice of itself. I hate it because it deprives our republican example of its just influence in the world—enables the enemies of free institutions, with plausibility, to taunt us as hypocrites—causes the real friends of freedom to doubt our sincerity, and especially because it forces so many really good men amongst ourselves into an open war with the very fundamental principles of civil liberty—criticizing the Declaration of Independence, and insisting that there is no right principle of action but self-interest.

Lehrman’s character portrait of Stephen Douglas, the architect of the Kansas-Nebraska Act, arouses both sympathy and repugnance. As Lincoln himself acknowledged, Douglas was a formidable opponent and a tireless warrior. Douglas’ policy for dealing with slavery was to remove any moral consideration of it from public debate and to place it out of the reach of federal interference, thereby leaving territorial settlers free to choose it or not, depending upon their particular interests, tastes, and circumstances. Lincoln characterized this ploy as “a false statesmanship that undertakes to build up a system of policy upon the basis of caring nothing about the very thing that every body does care the most about.” Thus, notes Lehrman, “did Lincoln impeach the proclaimed indifference toward slavery of Senator Douglas.” As Harry V. Jaffa has shown, Douglas, in effect, provided a nineteenth-century version of moral relativism that is so resonant with contemporary claims to moral neutrality in public life.

With designs on the presidency, Douglas sought to open a northern transcontinental railroad through the Kansas-Nebraska Territory where slavery had been banned by the Missouri Compromise. The South would never agree to a northern route, however, unless it received some concession in return. Seeking to accommodate both sides, Douglas proposed that the issue of the extension of slavery in the territories be resolved by the principle of popular sovereignty, “That the people of each State of this Union, and each Territory, with the view to its admission into the Union, have the right and ought to be permitted to enjoy its exercise, to form and regulate their domestic institutions, and internal matters in their own way, subject only to the Constitution.”

Initially, however, Douglas was reluctant explicitly to repeal the Missouri Compromise. He claimed that the principle of popular sovereignty affirmed by the more recent Compromise of 1850 superseded the older Missouri Compromise’s prohibition of slavery. Southern members, however, insisted upon an explicit repeal. Thus, to further his own ambition and to fatten his wallet, Douglas capitulated to Southern demands that it be expressly declared null and void. In exchange for this acquiescence, Secretary of War Jefferson Davis, future president of the Confederacy, agreed to persuade President Pierce to support the Kansas-Nebraska Act. Yet Douglas had strong premonitions of what was to follow: “I will incorporate [the express repeal] in my bill though I know it will raise a hell of a storm.”

Indeed it did. It marked a turning point in American history that fundamentally altered the political landscape of the time and the future course of the Republic. It led to the disintegration of traditional party loyalties between the Whigs and Democrats and precipitated a realignment, culminating in the formation of the new Republican Party—a coalition of northern antislavery Democrats and Whigs. In sum, the Kansas-Nebraska Act intensified sectional polarization, hurtling the country on a path towards civil war.

Through a close textual analysis, Lehrman traces the arc of Lincoln’s political thought before and after Peoria. He emphasizes that the defense of free labor and the “right to rise” constitutes the common denominator between the young Whig before Peoria and the mature statesman after it. Lehrman, himself a self-made man and entrepreneur, testifies to the promise of the American Dream extolled by Lincoln:

Born poor, Abraham Lincoln was truly a self-made man, believing as he said that “work, work, work is the main thing.” His economic policy was designed not only “to clear the path for all,” but to spell out incentives to encourage entrepreneurs to create new jobs, new products, new wealth. He believed in what historian Gabor Boritt has called “the right to rise.” Lincoln’s America was, in principle, a color-blind America. “I want every man to have the chance,” Lincoln announced in New Haven in March 1860, “and I believe a black man is entitled to it…when he may look forward to hope to be a hired laborer this year and the next, work for himself afterward, and finally to hire men to work for him! That is the true system.”

The Declaration of Independence comes to the fore at Peoria as “the bedrock upon which Lincoln in 1854 built his philosophical and political reasoning.” The second subtitle of Lehrman’s book is therefore appropriately named “Getting Right with the Declaration of Independence.” Lincoln, notes Lehrman, accorded the Declaration a constitutional status as a “formal congressional act of American union,” which “carried the force of law.” Indeed, it “was the first section in the Statutes of Indiana that Lincoln probably studied as a youth.” Preserving the Union for Lincoln thus always meant preserving the principles of the Declaration for which it stood.

In 1854 Douglas argued that slavery would eventually expire in the territories due to unsuitable climate and soil. This view stubbornly persists today, and Lehr-man takes sure aim at it. First, he notes that slavery was not necessarily wedded to agriculture; slave labor could be used, and was used, in factories. To further support this claim, Lehrman cites the authority of James McPherson, one of the leading Civil War historians of our time, who writes, “On the eve of the Civil War, plantation agriculture was more profitable, slavery more entrenched, slave owners more prosperous, and the ‘slave power’ more dominant within the South if not in the nation at large than it had ever been.” Thus does Lehrman impeach “the unnecessary war” thesis—namely, that the Civil War need not have been fought since slavery would have inevitably vanished on its own.

Lehrman deftly shows that what Lincoln and the opponents of slavery confronted in the mid-nineteenth century was not an innocent victim of “the war of northern aggression,” but an aggressive and militant slave power bent upon the extension of its peculiar institution, the nationalization of slavery, and a Caribbean slave empire. Throughout the book, he never lets the reader forget that at stake was the momentous question of whether or not the United States would become a slave or a free republic. The resolution of this issue in favor of freedom was by no means inevitable. It took determined moral leadership, beginning at Peoria, and, ultimately, the Civil War to resolve it. Throughout our history there will always be the likes of Stephen A. Douglas who seek to evade difficult moral issues through an appeal to relativism. The character of each generation may be measured in terms of whether or not we choose to confront these issues in the manner of Douglas or of Lincoln.

By including a copy of the speech in its entirety, Lehrman invites us to read the Peoria Address for ourselves as we contemplate the moral meaning of our regime on the bicentennial in 2009 of the birth of its greatest spokesman—Abraham Lincoln. On this patriotic occasion, Lehrman provides a fitting tribute, reminding us that “The Peoria speech had set Lincoln on the road to the Emancipation Proclamation.”

Joseph A. Fornieri is Professor of Political Science at the Rochester Institute of Technology and the author of Abraham Lincoln’s Political Faith (2003), a work that explores Lincoln’s civil theology and his combination of religion and politics. This reveiew was originally published in the Intercollegiate Review, Spring 2009, copyright 2009 by the Intercollegiate Studies Institute (ISI). The website for ISI is: www.isi.org

THE MORAL MEANING OF AMERICA: A REVIEW OF “LINCOLN AT PEORIA….”

“Throughout our history there will always be the likes of Stephen A. Douglas who seek to evade difficult moral issues through an appeal to relativism. The character of each generation may be measured in terms of whether or not we choose to confront these issues in the manner of Douglas or of Lincoln.” –an excerpt from this essay

by Joseph R. Fornieri, Professor of Political Science, Rochester Institute of Technology

A review of Lincoln at Peoria: The Turning Point: Getting Right with the Declaration of Independence by Lewis E. Lehrman (Mechanicsburg, PA: Stackpole Books, 2008) from Intercollegiate Review, Spring 2009

What is Abraham Lincoln’s greatest speech? An obvious case can be made for the Gettysburg Address, which distills the essence of the American creed and has come to represent the catechism of our civil religion, “of the people, by the people, for the people.” Others claim that the honor belongs to the Second Inaugural Address. In that national sermon, Lincoln pondered the meaning of the Civil War in view of God’s providence. The speech culminates in a magnanimous call to righteousness and reconciliation: “With malice toward none, with charity for all, with firmness in the right as God gives us to see the right, let us strive on to finish the work we are in, to bind up the nation’s wounds.” Still others argue that the Cooper Union Address was Lincoln’s greatest since it was “the speech that made him president”: “Let us have faith that right makes might, and in that faith, let us, to the end, dare to do our duty as we understand it.”

Notwithstanding these others, if one were placed in the unenviable position of having to choose Lincoln’s greatest, I would cast my vote for the Peoria Address of October 16, 1854. At Peoria, Lincoln cogently articulated the core antislavery convictions that would guide his statesmanship for the rest of his life. This articulation involved a corresponding vindication of self-government and the Union. In a word, the Peoria Address constituted the most mature and vivid expression of Lincoln’s political faith or ultimate moral justification of American public life based upon the principles of the Declaration. Indeed, Lincoln’s subsequent speeches and writings drew upon the comprehensive and foundational antislavery teachings he expounded at Peoria.

It is therefore surprising that in the voluminous Lincoln literature there has been no full-length, single-volume treatment of this critical speech. Though it was recognized by Lincoln’s contemporaries as a tour de force, it has since been eclipsed by attention given to his other major speeches. In Lincoln at Peoria: The Turning Point, Lewis Lehrman remedies this omission by persuasively showing us why the Peoria Address deserves its rightful place as one of Lincoln’s greatest statements. Lehrman’s meticulously researched and elegantly written book makes a significant contribution towards enhancing our understanding of the moral dimensions of Lincoln’s political thought and statesmanship. It is highly recommended for students and scholars alike.

Lehrman’s outstanding study integrates and builds upon insights from the fields of history, political science, and political philosophy. He begins by tracing the historical and political context of the Peoria Address as a response to the infamous Kansas-Nebraska Act of 1854 that repealed the Missouri Compromise of 1820. This latter measure had maintained a fragile sectional peace for more than thirty years by drawing a line through the remaining territories of the Louisiana Purchase: slavery was banned north of 36˚30’ but tolerated south of it. The repeal of the Missouri Compromise stirred Lincoln to reenter politics in response to a new militancy of the proslavery forces that threatened both the moral and territorial integrity of the Union. “I was losing interest in politics,” he declared, “when the Missouri Compromise aroused me again.”

The Peoria Address can be seen as a prelude to the famous Lincoln-Douglas debates of 1858. It was at Peoria in 1854 where the two titans first crossed swords over slavery and popular sovereignty. At Peoria, in response to the Kansas-Nebraska Act, Lincoln offered his first comprehensive indictment of slavery and defense of America’s free institutions. After Peoria, he would emerge as the standard-bearer of the antislavery Republican Party in Illinois and ultimately the president of the United States in 1860. “The three-hour Peoria speech was a magisterial tour of antislavery principles, their constitutional and legislative history, and the antislavery policies of the federal government from the Founding through the Kansas-Nebraska Act,” Lehrman writes. “At this turning point in American history, Lincoln queried whether America was destined to become a free-soil republic or a slaveholding nation. Throughout his remarks, he celebrated the intent of the Founders to put slavery in the course of ultimate extinction.”

Lehrman tells the story of this turning point in an engaging narrative that brings to life the cast of characters of the Civil War era: Lincoln, Douglas, Chase, Seward, Stevens, Davis. Though much has been made of Lincoln’s ambition or melancholy as a spur to his greatness, Lehrman reminds us that more principled motives were at work as well. Those who would deny the sincerity and depth of Lincoln’s hatred of slavery and his corresponding patriotic devotion to the American experiment are confronted in Lehrman’s superb book with a mountain of evidence to the contrary, as when Lincoln exclaimed:

This declared indifference [of popular sovereignty to the evil of slavery], but as I must think, covert real zeal for the spread of slavery, I can not but hate. I hate it because of the monstrous injustice of itself. I hate it because it deprives our republican example of its just influence in the world—enables the enemies of free institutions, with plausibility, to taunt us as hypocrites—causes the real friends of freedom to doubt our sincerity, and especially because it forces so many really good men amongst ourselves into an open war with the very fundamental principles of civil liberty—criticizing the Declaration of Independence, and insisting that there is no right principle of action but self-interest.

Lehrman’s character portrait of Stephen Douglas, the architect of the Kansas-Nebraska Act, arouses both sympathy and repugnance. As Lincoln himself acknowledged, Douglas was a formidable opponent and a tireless warrior. Douglas’ policy for dealing with slavery was to remove any moral consideration of it from public debate and to place it out of the reach of federal interference, thereby leaving territorial settlers free to choose it or not, depending upon their particular interests, tastes, and circumstances. Lincoln characterized this ploy as “a false statesmanship that undertakes to build up a system of policy upon the basis of caring nothing about the very thing that every body does care the most about.” Thus, notes Lehrman, “did Lincoln impeach the proclaimed indifference toward slavery of Senator Douglas.” As Harry V. Jaffa has shown, Douglas, in effect, provided a nineteenth-century version of moral relativism that is so resonant with contemporary claims to moral neutrality in public life.

With designs on the presidency, Douglas sought to open a northern transcontinental railroad through the Kansas-Nebraska Territory where slavery had been banned by the Missouri Compromise. The South would never agree to a northern route, however, unless it received some concession in return. Seeking to accommodate both sides, Douglas proposed that the issue of the extension of slavery in the territories be resolved by the principle of popular sovereignty, “That the people of each State of this Union, and each Territory, with the view to its admission into the Union, have the right and ought to be permitted to enjoy its exercise, to form and regulate their domestic institutions, and internal matters in their own way, subject only to the Constitution.”

Initially, however, Douglas was reluctant explicitly to repeal the Missouri Compromise. He claimed that the principle of popular sovereignty affirmed by the more recent Compromise of 1850 superseded the older Missouri Compromise’s prohibition of slavery. Southern members, however, insisted upon an explicit repeal. Thus, to further his own ambition and to fatten his wallet, Douglas capitulated to Southern demands that it be expressly declared null and void. In exchange for this acquiescence, Secretary of War Jefferson Davis, future president of the Confederacy, agreed to persuade President Pierce to support the Kansas-Nebraska Act. Yet Douglas had strong premonitions of what was to follow: “I will incorporate [the express repeal] in my bill though I know it will raise a hell of a storm.”

Indeed it did. It marked a turning point in American history that fundamentally altered the political landscape of the time and the future course of the Republic. It led to the disintegration of traditional party loyalties between the Whigs and Democrats and precipitated a realignment, culminating in the formation of the new Republican Party—a coalition of northern antislavery Democrats and Whigs. In sum, the Kansas-Nebraska Act intensified sectional polarization, hurtling the country on a path towards civil war.

Through a close textual analysis, Lehrman traces the arc of Lincoln’s political thought before and after Peoria. He emphasizes that the defense of free labor and the “right to rise” constitutes the common denominator between the young Whig before Peoria and the mature statesman after it. Lehrman, himself a self-made man and entrepreneur, testifies to the promise of the American Dream extolled by Lincoln:

Born poor, Abraham Lincoln was truly a self-made man, believing as he said that “work, work, work is the main thing.” His economic policy was designed not only “to clear the path for all,” but to spell out incentives to encourage entrepreneurs to create new jobs, new products, new wealth. He believed in what historian Gabor Boritt has called “the right to rise.” Lincoln’s America was, in principle, a color-blind America. “I want every man to have the chance,” Lincoln announced in New Haven in March 1860, “and I believe a black man is entitled to it…when he may look forward to hope to be a hired laborer this year and the next, work for himself afterward, and finally to hire men to work for him! That is the true system.”

The Declaration of Independence comes to the fore at Peoria as “the bedrock upon which Lincoln in 1854 built his philosophical and political reasoning.” The second subtitle of Lehrman’s book is therefore appropriately named “Getting Right with the Declaration of Independence.” Lincoln, notes Lehrman, accorded the Declaration a constitutional status as a “formal congressional act of American union,” which “carried the force of law.” Indeed, it “was the first section in the Statutes of Indiana that Lincoln probably studied as a youth.” Preserving the Union for Lincoln thus always meant preserving the principles of the Declaration for which it stood.

In 1854 Douglas argued that slavery would eventually expire in the territories due to unsuitable climate and soil. This view stubbornly persists today, and Lehr-man takes sure aim at it. First, he notes that slavery was not necessarily wedded to agriculture; slave labor could be used, and was used, in factories. To further support this claim, Lehrman cites the authority of James McPherson, one of the leading Civil War historians of our time, who writes, “On the eve of the Civil War, plantation agriculture was more profitable, slavery more entrenched, slave owners more prosperous, and the ‘slave power’ more dominant within the South if not in the nation at large than it had ever been.” Thus does Lehrman impeach “the unnecessary war” thesis—namely, that the Civil War need not have been fought since slavery would have inevitably vanished on its own.

Lehrman deftly shows that what Lincoln and the opponents of slavery confronted in the mid-nineteenth century was not an innocent victim of “the war of northern aggression,” but an aggressive and militant slave power bent upon the extension of its peculiar institution, the nationalization of slavery, and a Caribbean slave empire. Throughout the book, he never lets the reader forget that at stake was the momentous question of whether or not the United States would become a slave or a free republic. The resolution of this issue in favor of freedom was by no means inevitable. It took determined moral leadership, beginning at Peoria, and, ultimately, the Civil War to resolve it. Throughout our history there will always be the likes of Stephen A. Douglas who seek to evade difficult moral issues through an appeal to relativism. The character of each generation may be measured in terms of whether or not we choose to confront these issues in the manner of Douglas or of Lincoln.

By including a copy of the speech in its entirety, Lehrman invites us to read the Peoria Address for ourselves as we contemplate the moral meaning of our regime on the bicentennial in 2009 of the birth of its greatest spokesman—Abraham Lincoln. On this patriotic occasion, Lehrman provides a fitting tribute, reminding us that “The Peoria speech had set Lincoln on the road to the Emancipation Proclamation.”

Joseph A. Fornieri is Professor of Political Science at the Rochester Institute of Technology and the author of Abraham Lincoln’s Political Faith (2003), a work that explores Lincoln’s civil theology and his combination of religion and politics. This reveiew was originally published in the Intercollegiate Review, Spring 2009, copyright 2009 by the Intercollegiate Studies Institute (ISI). The website for ISI is: www.isi.org

EQUALLY NOT NOTHING, A REVIEW OF “THE CHRISTIAN REVOLUTION AND ITS FASHIONABLE ENEMIES”

“…what our new atheists regard as modern progress in the direction of rational liberation is itself a reactionary superstition. The modern Enlightenment has actually been a rebellion against the whole truth about our natures, about who we are, and about the true source of our freedom and dignity….The sentimental preferences of our atheists are really those of a Christianity without Christ.” –an excerpt from this review

by Peter Augustine Lawler, Professor of Government at Berry College

A review of Atheist Delusions: The Christian Revolution and Its Fashionable Enemies
by David Bentley Hart (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 2009) from Intercollegiate Review, Fall 2010

This brilliant, stunningly erudite, and powerfully provocative work begins as a tough criticism of the naive stupidity of the books of our popularizing “new atheists”—the likes of Christopher Hitchens, Richard Dawkins, and Daniel Dennett. Those best-selling authors have made atheism newly fashionable by spinning it shamelessly to appeal to our “sophisticated” prejudices. They criticize the immoral effects of Christianity from an anti-cruelty, pro-freedom, pro-Enlightenment perspective. They paint a historical picture of the scientifically advanced civilizations of the ancient Greeks and Romans, reasonably adorned with an easygoing polytheism. That admirable world was ruined, they explain, by the repressive disruption occasioned by the superstitious belief that there is only one, true, personal God.

Hart’s “governing conviction” is that what our new atheists regard as modern progress in the direction of rational liberation is itself a reactionary superstition. The modern Enlightenment has actually been a rebellion against the whole truth about our natures, about who we are, and about the true source of our freedom and dignity. And that rebellion has been not so much radical as selective and self-indulgent. By compassionately privileging personal freedom and human rights over what they believe they know through science, the new atheists remain parasitic on the key Christian insight about who we are. Their attachment to the humane virtues makes no sense outside the Christian claim for the unique and irreplaceable dignity of every human person. That claim is completely unsupported by either ancient (Aristotelian) or modern (Darwinian) science. The sentimental preferences of our atheists are really those of a Christianity without Christ.

Hart repeatedly highlights, and shares, the contempt of the old atheist Nietzsche for the cowardly unsustainability of such groundless preferences. It was Nietzsche who prophesied that our fading, subjective experiences of dignity, freedom, and love have a very limited future as merely beneficial illusions. It was Nietzsche, “the most prescient philosopher of nihilism,” who predicted the coming of a world full of Last Men lacking the great aspirations or profound longings that are the foundation of cultural creativity. For Hart, what follows Christianity is inevitably a post-Christian world that’s all about nothing. Still, much more than Nietzsche, Hart sees the pre-Christian world as also, in a different way, being all about nothing.

Hart describes for us a pre-Christian world that was cruel and capricious— reminding us forcefully of the torture and murder that ancient paganism tolerated as a matter of course, precisely because it regarded particular persons as unreal. The truth was best seen by the philosopher who became dead to himself, who resigned himself to the ephemeral insignificance of his particular existence. Christianity was, in a way, the slave revolt Nietzsche described, a “cosmic rebellion” against the enslavement of each of us to natural and political necessity. Christ, the Christians claimed, freed us from the limitations of our merely biological natures through his perfect reconciliation of God’s nature and man’s nature. He was, the Nicene fathers concluded, fully God and fully man, and his redemption was to divinize every man. Christ freed each of us for unlimited love for every other person made in God’s image; Christ was the foundation of a virtuous way of life based on a vision of the good that has no pagan counterpart. Charity to all became the virtue most in accord with the truth about who we are. For Hart, the wonder is that anyone could have imagined the ideals of the Christian faith in the first place, given that those ideals had so little support in any pre-Christian conception of who we are.

It is barely too strong to say that, for Hart, Christ transformed each of us from being nobody to being somebody—indeed, a somebody of infinite value. None of us is destined to be a slave, and death has been overcome. We are no longer defined by our merely biological natures, because our nature is now to be both human and divine. From one view, there is no empirical evidence that death has been overcome for each particular human being. From another, the evidence is the unprecedented virtue flowing from the unconditional love present among the early Christians and that virtue’s indirect, historical transformation of the broader social and political world. The change in who we are is the result of a deepened human inwardness or self-consciousness: Christ made each of us irreducibly deeper by infusing divinity into every nook and cranny of our natures.

Every feature of the personal liberation praised by our new atheists and our egalitarian autonomy boosters generally came into the world in Christian communities. Even the Stoics didn’t approach the Christians in their indifference to a person’s social status. The Christians were the first to be completely opposed to slavery; the first for raising women to equality in marriage and elsewhere; the first for faithfulness in monogamous marriage; the first for the egalitarian brotherhood of all men. For the Christians, the community of personal love wasn’t some otherworldly hope. Rather, that community was formed by obligations given to divinized beings here and now. Our divinization through Christ includes what is called life after death, but we can live lovingly liberated from death even before we die.

A big difference between Hart and Nietzsche, it should go without saying, is that Hart doesn’t hate the modern world insofar as it is a Christian accomplishment. There is ennobling truth in the egalitarianism of secular Christianity; our secularism is not simply the emptying out of all human content from our lives. Nevertheless, Hart should make clearer than he does that he actually affirms much of what’s called modern social progress in the direction of the liberation of women, the technological liberation of many from mere subsistence, the erosion of unjust conventional hierarchies, and even the affirmation of universal human rights. The modern abolitionists and the fervent partisans of civil rights, Hart repeatedly observes, were either Christians or consciously inspired by Christianity. Liberty without love is an illusion, or at least a distortion, and there’s no denying that modern political liberation was often inspired by a love for free beings, as well as by the love of being free.

Still, Hart never forgets that the effects of Christianity on political life are always incomplete and compromised. That was true of both the Roman Empire and imperial Christendom, as well as the British and American empires. The polis or nation or empire can be influenced or limited by the presence of the Christian community, but always against politics’ own grain. Hart’s view seems to be that all political life is unworthy of divinized beings, and part of our true liberation is from politics’ “inherent violence.” For Hart, it was a tragedy that the church as an institution ever played a role in political life or assumed responsibility for national or imperial unity—and so he has little nostalgia for the comprehensive dream that was Christendom. Much of his book is a description of “the history of a constant struggle between the power of the gospel to alter and shape society and the power of the state to absorb every useful institution into itself.” But he should have made clearer that the modern separation of the nation from the church—in, for example, the American case—cannot be regarded as a tragedy for the church, so long as the gospel has retained some influence. The separation of church and state, Hart acknowledges, is a distinctively Christian accomplishment. The tragedy, of course, was the nation’s eventual liberation from Christianity’s chastening influence—a liberation, Hart should have added, that is surely least complete in America.

The Christian view that our freedom is for love’s sake also included the thought that we cannot and should not change our God-given natures; we are, by nature, divinized beings free from merely biological limitations and so free for deathless, unconditioned love. The post-Christian affirms that we are meant to be free, but without any sense that we have been freed from death or necessity. So our freedom is to be used to win, by our own efforts, what the Christian God had promised to provide. Loving unconditionally from faith in an imaginary divinity is for suckers, but there’s no denying that this faith showed us that we are, in fact, free—and we won’t be satisfied until we’ve used that freedom to overcome death for ourselves. We are not, by nature, divine beings: there’s no evidence for that without faith. But perhaps we can employ our freedom to make ourselves divine—free from the impersonal limits of our biological natures. The modern thought is that faith in God can be replaced by a more reasonable faith in the unprecedented historical future, faith in what we can do for ourselves in a basically hostile world.

Having been given nothing that corresponds to the high opinion he has of his personal significance (which he learned, indirectly, from Christianity), the anxious modern person believes, nihilistically, that he is on his own to make his world worthy of him. He is not nihilistic, we might say, in his own case. No Christian or post-Christian is nihilistic in his own case, and his “delusion” concerning his own personal significance is at the core of the always-futile Aristotelian (Straussian) and Darwinian criticisms of the basically Christian pretensions of all modern persons. The secular Christian incoherence that Hart repeatedly criticizes is that no person is really a materialist in his own case, even though he “knows” he has no scientific reason why he should not be. From one view, modern nihilism always amounts to the position that, after the revelation or discovery of the Christian insight about personal freedom, the individual person is a persistent, irreducibly mysterious leftover from the world described by science. How can the person be happy or secure while believing personal love—love worthy of me—and personal existence itself are, objectively, illusions? It is little wonder that Christianity without Christ leads to the conclusion that we should transform nature—and especially our own natures—to be worthy of our freedom.

It is not Hart’s intention to provide aid and comfort to those—from new atheists to conservative Darwinians, Straussians, and many Heideggerians—who wish that Christianity had never had such a profound influence in the world. But he does say that after Christ’s incarnation the alternatives are Christianity or nothing, and he sees no prospect of reversing the declining cultural influence of Christianity anytime soon. There can be no return to the prudence of the ancient world, which was based on an insight about our natural limitations that is rejected by free persons. There seems to be no return, for now, to a widespread belief that our natures have
been freed from death by the divine gift of the incarnation of God. In Hart’s view, the Christian insight about who we are will not completely disappear, but its future for now will be in small countercultural communities that will be increasingly alienated from a world that will be dominated, at best, by apathetic Last Men and at worst by eugenic transformationalists employing all means necessary to win our final freedom from nature. Christianity discredited every other understanding of god or human idealism, and so in the absence of Christ—Nietzsche and Hart agree—God more or less inevitably seems dead.

Hart says in one place that the genius of Christianity lies in its extremism. Christians contrast the intractable selfishness, cruelty, violence, and melancholic hopelessness of our merely biological natures with the unconditioned personal love that can govern our divinized nature. Hart sometimes seems to say that Aristotle was right, in his time, about our ultimate enslavement to an impersonal logos that negates every aspiration for personal significance; then, Christ transformed us— changing our natures. But surely Christians believe that, from the beginning, the world and each of us was a divine gift. And, from the beginning, human experience was, finally, that logos is only present in persons. Only persons are open to the truth about being and human being. The Christian insight opened our eyes more fully to what we can see for ourselves about the ground for personal freedom in being itself. The personal logos affirmed by the church fathers was always more true than the impersonal logos affirmed by Aristotle and Darwin.

That’s why we can say with some confidence that both Nietzsche and Hart exaggerate by describing persons today as Last Men or beings without human content or nothing—emotionally puerile and flat-souled mere consumers. And that’s why we can be more hopeful about the political and cultural future of the human person than Hart seems to be. That our world is inescapably Christian or post-Christian is more good news than not about our inescapably human future. We know we are all equally not nothing, and it’s not in our power to negate that truth. Still, we can and will, as Hart rightly shows, make ourselves (and others) miserable trying.

Peter Augustine Lawler is Dana Professor of Government at Berry College. He teaches courses in political philosophy and American politics. He is executive editor of the quarterly journal, Perspectives on Political Science and has written or edited fifteen books. His newest book is Modern and American Dignity (ISI Books, 2010), for which he was named a Georgia Author of the Year. All his books–such as Postmodernism Rightly UnderstoodAliens in AmericaStuck with Virtue, and Homeless and at Home in America, have been widely and positively reviewed. He was the 2007 winner of the Weaver Prize for Scholarly Excellence in promoting human dignity to a broad audience.

This review is republished from the Fall, 2010 edition of Intercollegiate Review, published by the Intercollegiate Studies Institute (ISI). Copyright 2010. Used by permission. ISI is a nonprofit, nonpartisan, tax-exempt educational organization that seeks to educate future leaders in the timeless principles that make America free and prosperous—the core ideas behind the free market, the American Founding, and Western civilization that are rarely taught in the classroom. The website address of ISI is: http://home.isi.org

THE GREAT OMISSION

By Major Kevin Cutright, U.S. Army

For a few years, I have been uncomfortable with the prayers offered for deployed soldiers. As I bow my head and listen to the plea for protection or the gratitude for it, I share the sentiment, but I also hear a great omission. Where is the plea for the success of their efforts? Our leaders are staking our long-term security on crafting societies that have no room for terrorists, that will condemn instead of endorse violence in the name of religion or politics. Where are the prayers for those communities?

Some resist praying for non-Christians, as if prayer should be spent only on believers. This excuse involves an economy of prayer in which blessings are parsed out by a god whose powers are limited.

Some consider all Iraqis and Afghans terrorists, or at least complicit in terrorism. This ridiculous notion may understandably take root in the minds of soldiers threatened by insurgents who are indistinguishable from civilians (I had to stamp it out of my unit and myself in 2003, and to a lesser extent in 2009), but it’s indefensible among American Christians on the homefront. We have had leaders smart enough to separate the “reconcilables” from the hardened terrorists; why have we failed to reflect this in our prayers?

Some see the efforts in Iraq and Afghanistan as too ambitious, having far too little chance for success. This would seem to warrant more prayer, though, not less.

For many of us, I think the great omission stems from something simpler and more condemning: we don’t have room in our hearts to yearn for anything beyond self-security. Inside and outside the uniform, we just never think about the Iraqis’ or Afghans’ plight. We have let 9/11 justify a zero-sum mentality that rules out the wellbeing of others. This lack of sympathetic imagination bothers me most. It’s an error of the heart instead of merely an error in logic.

This omission is not new. One enduring effect of the Cold War is precisely the stark “us vs. them” calculus brought on by Mutually Assured Destruction. But counterinsurgencies do not allow the concession to self-interest cautiously defended by Judeo-Christian thinkers in supreme emergencies. Countering violent insurgents requires both military and political action working in concert. We don’t have the luxury of relying solely on military advantage to win. Local civilians must envision a better future with the supported government than with the guerrillas. Failing to keep their well-being in our prayers, and thus removed from our passions and actions, becomes a critical strategic shortcoming. We cannot credibly criticize Iraqis or Afghans that refuse to cooperate with soldiers who clearly have no sympathy for them.

As our military leaves Iraq, our prayers don’t have to. Will we pray not only for the protection of thousands in our embassy and consulates, but also for their success in nurturing the well-being of all Iraqis? And, can we expand our prayers for protection to the thousands of Iraqis who remain at risk for aiding our soldiers, as Kirk Johnson recently pointed out in the NY Times? The costs involved in the last eight years should strongly motivate us to pray for Iraq’s success, to make the loss of so many and so much worth it.

The great omission is a strange absence. I yearn for the chapel service that overcomes it and guides my heart to the well-being of those we claimed to be helping. While teaching at West Point, I attended services where we dutifully prayed every week for American divisions deployed, displaying the unit’s guidon next to the podium. We need to do that; yet, I also think we should display the guidon of that division’s counterpart host nation unit. God’s love for all the world demands that we pray for our allies and enemies as well as ourselves.

Kevin Cutright is a student at the U.S. Army Command and General Staff College at Fort Leavenworth, Kansas. He served twice in Iraq, first as a field artillery battery commander and later as an advisor to Iraqi security forces. He taught philosophy at the U.S. Military Academy, where he also served as an officer sponsor of the Navigators ministry.